(redirected from Cardinal numbers)

[Home]Cardinal number

HomePage | Recent Changes | Preferences

Two sets X and Y are said to have the same cardinality if there exists a bijection between X and Y; we then write | X | = | Y |. The cardinal number itself is often defined as the least ordinal number a with | a | = | X |. A cardinal number is often called simply a cardinal.

Motivation

The intuitive idea of a cardinal is to create some notion of the relative size or "bigness" of a set without reference to the kind of members which it has. For finite sets this is easy; one simply counts the number of elements a set has. In order to compare the sizes of larger sets, its necessary to appeal to more subtle notions.

A set Y is at least as big as a set X if there is a one-to-one mapping from the elements of X to the elements of Y. This is most easily understood by an example; suppose we have the sets X = {1,2,3} and Y = {5,6,7,8}, then using this notion of size we would observe that there is a mapping:

 1 -> 5
 2 -> 6
 3 -> 7
which is one-to-one, and hence conclude that Y has cardinality greater than or equal to X. The advantage of this notion is that it can be extended to infinite sets.

The classic example used is that of the infinite hotel paradox. Suppose you are a innkeeper at a hotel with an infinite number of rooms. The hotel is full, and then a new guest arrives. It's possible to fit the extra guest in by asking the guest who was in room 1 to move to room 2, the guest in room 2 to move to room 3, and so on, leaving room 1 vacant. In this way we can see that the set {1,2,3,...} has the same cardinality as the set {2,3,4,...} since a one-to-one mapping from the first to the second has been shown. This motivates the defintion of an infinite set being any set which has a proper subset of the same cardinality; in this case {2,3,4,...} is a proper subset of {1,2,3,...}.

It is provable that the cardinality of the real numbers is greater than that of the natural numbers just described. This is easily visualized using Cantor's diagonal argument; classic questions of cardinality (for instance the continuum hypothesis) are concerned with discovering whether there is some cardinal between some pair of other infinite cardinals. In more recent times mathematicians have been describing the properties of larger and larger cardinals.

Formal Definition

Formally, the order among cardinal numbers is defined as follows: | X | <= | Y | means that there exists an injective function from X to Y. The [Cantor-Bernstein-Schroeder theorem]? states that if | X | <= | Y | and | Y | <= | X | then | X | = | Y |. The axiom of choice is equivalent to the statement that given two sets X and Y, either | X | <= | Y | or | Y | <= | X |.

A set X is infinite?, or equivalently, its cardinal is infinite?, if there exists a proper subset Y of X with | X | = | Y |. A cardinal which is not infinite is called finite; it can then be proved that the finite cardinals are just the natural numbers, i.e., that a set X is finite if and only if | X | = | n | = n for some natural number n. It can also be proved that the cardinal aleph-0 (where aleph is the first letter in the Hebrew alphabet) of the set of natural numbers is the smallest infinite cardinal, i.e., that any infinite set admits a subset of cardinality aleph-0. The next larger cardinal is denoted by aleph-1 and so on. For every ordinal a there is a cardinal number aleph-a, and this list exhausts all cardinal numbers.

Note that without the axiom of choice there are sets which can not be well-ordered, and the definition of cardinal number given above does not work. It is still possible to define cardinal numbers (a mapping from sets to sets such that sets with the same cardinality have the same image), but it is slightly more complicated. One can also easily study cardinality without refering to cardinal numbers.

If X and Y are disjoint, the cardinal of the union of X and Y is called | X | + | Y |. We also define the product of cardinals by | X | x | Y | = | X x Y | (the product on the right hand side is the cartesian product). Also | X || Y | = | XY | where XY is defined as the set of all functions from Y to X. It can be shown that for finite cardinals these operations coincide with the usual operations for natural numbers. For infinite sets (assuming the axiom of choice) we have | X | + | Y | = | X | x | Y | = max{| X |, | Y |}. On the other hand, 2| X | is the cardinality of the power set of the set X and Cantors Diagonal argument shows that 2| X | > | X | for any set X. This proves that there exists no largest cardinal. In fact, the class of cardinals is a proper class.

The continuum hypothesis states that there are no cardinals strictly between aleph-0 and 2aleph-0. The latter cardinal number is also often denoted by c; it is the cardinality the set of real numbers, or the continuum, whence the name. The generalized continuum hypothesis states that there are no cardinals strictly between | X | and 2| X | for arbitrary infinite X. The continuum hypothesis is independent from the usual axioms of set theory, the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms together with the axiom of choice (ZFC).

Inaccessible, Hyperinaccessible and Mahlo Cardinals

A cardinal k > aleph-0 is (weakly) inaccessible if the following conditions hold:

A cardinal k > aleph-0 is strongly inaccessible if the following conditions hold:

It is provably impossible to prove the existence of strongly inaccessible cardinals in ZFC. It is an open question whether their non-existence can be proved; most people believe that it cannot. The same is true for all the classes of cardinals that follow:

A cardinal is 0-hyperinaccessible if it is a weakly inaccesible cardinal.

A cardinal A is 1-hyperinaccessible if there are A inaccessibles less than A.

A cardinal B is (n+1)-hyperinaccessible if B is an n-hyperinaccesible preceeded by B n-hyperinaccessibles.

A cardinal C is hyper-hyperinaccessible (or hyper2-inaccessible) if C is n-hyperinaccessible for all n < C.

A cardinal D is 1-hyper2-inaccessible if there are D hyper2-inaccessible cardinals less than D.

A cardinal E is hyper3-inaccessible if E is n-hyper2-inaccessible for all n < E.

A cardinal F is super-hyperinaccessibles if F is preceeded by F hypern-inaccessibles for every n less than F.

A cardinal G which is preceeded by G inaccessible cardinals, G hyper-inaccessibles cardinals, G super-hyper-inaccessible cardinals, and so forth (continue the above construction) is called a Mahlo cardinal, after Mahlo who discovered them in 1911.

The existence of Mahlo cardinals cannot be proved from the ZFC axioms, though they have not been proved not to exist either. They are useful in boolean relation theory.

Indescribable cardinals are cardinals much bigger than Mahlo cardinals.

Reference: http://logweb.terrashare.com/text/logic/infini.txt


/Talk

HomePage | Recent Changes | Preferences
This page is read-only | View other revisions
Last edited December 14, 2001 3:45 am by AxelBoldt (diff)
Search: